CATEGORII DOCUMENTE |
Bulgara | Ceha slovaca | Croata | Engleza | Estona | Finlandeza | Franceza |
Germana | Italiana | Letona | Lituaniana | Maghiara | Olandeza | Poloneza |
Sarba | Slovena | Spaniola | Suedeza | Turca | Ucraineana |
DOCUMENTE SIMILARE |
||||||
|
||||||
TERMENI importanti pentru acest document |
||||||
Animal Communication
Throughout this course of study, the concept of
language as the demarcation between animals and humans has prevailed. Further,
as we have seen in our class readings, many claim that it is through language
that our 'consciousness' and 'cognitive' skills are
developed. Accordingly, these skills are necessary for us to interpret and
conceptualize our world. What this infers is that because we have these skills
and the 'brute' animals do not, animals do not possess the ability to
analyze or think about their world. When presented in this manner, I was almost
convinced that this was a plausible representation of mental development.
However, I found that I still had a nagging feeling that it could not be true.
Upon further investigation I found that language is by no means the only way to
interpret or communicate in the world. The significance of this statement is
that if my thesis proves valid the results are twofold: it refutes the
behaviorists and Cartesian assertion that language is the boundary that
separates animals and humans; and it supports the theory that animals not only
have language, but they also posses the ability for cognitive thought.
No one will argue that animals possess sight and auditory abilities. However,
the concept that animals have language and are capable of thought for some is a
bitter pill to swollow. I believe that they are also
capable of thought and even intention. Granted, the development of language is
often used as a gauge of mental aptitude in humans: 'Language competence
is intimately tied to, or maybe even definitive of, our concept of human
mentality' (Atherton and Schwartz, 137).
However, while language is an asset which enables people to conceptualize their
world, it is by no means a necessity. This is demonstrated by the ability of
physically handicapped persons (e.g., the deaf) and mentally handicapped
persons (e.g., victims of cerebral palsy) to communicate using symbols. It is
also demonstrated by the reliance on kinesics, body
language, in young children. Numerous studies attest to the ability of apes and
baboons to communicate using symbols and body language. These studies are the
first steps in proving the existence of animal mentation.
Griffin argues that many scientists do not accept the notion of animal mentation because of the difficulty of defining abstract
concepts such as 'consciousness' and 'mind' (Griffin 163).
In reviewing the works of other scholars, Griffin puts forth some working
definitions. The concept of mind 'Encompasses sense perception, feeling
and emotion, traits of character and personality, and the volitional aspects of
human life, as well as the more narrowly intellectual phenomena' (Griffin
163). Consciousness in an entity suggests 'an organism which can have
intentions the ability to form a plan, and make a decision to adopt the
plan' (Griffin 164). Although these terms are defined by their human
references, studies indicate that animals, and even insects, demonstrate
emotion, volition, and planning in their daily lives. For example, the
communicative dances of honeybees convey multi-level messages that suggest
conscious thought and the incorporation of new information (Griffin 178).
Similarly, wild vervet monkeys have a system whihc allows them to alert others in their group to
potential danger. Diamond states that they 'have a natural form of
symbolic communication based on grunts, with slightly different grunts to mean
'leopard,' eagle,' and 'snake.' (Diamond 55). What is
significant is that the concept of volition is also evident vervet
monkeys when they 'fake' a grunt in order to scatter the other
monkeys away from food. Hence, volition and communication should not be
considered unique to the human animal.
The ability to manipulate objects and to investigate new information is
considered another hallmark of the intellectual development unique to humans.
However children, as well as animals are capable of 'learning' these
traits equally as well. According to Piaget, the
child is like a little scientist who 'almost from birth touches objects,
manipulates them, turns them around, looks at them, and in these ways he
develops an increasing understanding of their properties' (Wood 35). The
understanding comes, in part, from 'referring to preceding observables which are related to the object; or inferring
the relations between an action and a reaction, but the input is always from
observable material contents' (Piaget 171). All
this is accomplished without the benefit of language. It is not necessary to
communicate verbally to a child presented with a new object how to incorporate
that object into its existing schemes. The ability to incorporate new
information is a sign of the child's development of mental aptitude. Further,
countless examples of this new information incorporation idea was observed by
Savage-Rumbaugh in 'Kanzi'.
In particular, the experiment that allowed the apes to see themselves on
television. All of the apes responded with individual ideosyncrosities
when presented with the seeing themselves and 'knowing' who they were
observing on the television. Additionally, Savage-Rumbaugh
relates similar events associated with hand mirrors that were given to the
apes.
According to Piaget, a child's first communication
occurs, not by language, but by 'acted conversations' (Wood 181).
Children use a variety of pointing, waving, and gyration motions to indicate
what is on their minds. Even after a child makes initial attempts at speech,
understanding his or her body language is critical in deciphering the intent of
the communication. Wood points out that 'Younger children depend on
gestures and bodily movement for a direct statement of their message. With the
acquisition of verbal language, gestures and movements take on the different
role of complementing the verbal message' (Wood 182). For example a
toddler who wants a cookie might stand in front of the cookie jar, point to it,
and grunt. The body language reinforces the clarity of the child's message.
That language is not indispensable is demonstrated by the fact that children
often comprehend much more than their language skills imply. Jackendoff's studies indicate that 'children have some
grasp of the grammatical patterns of the language quite a while before they can
use them in their own speech children use this grasp to help them figure
out what we're trying to tell them, even when they don't know all the words
we've uttered' (Jackendoff 107). Therefore,
although a child might have a vocabulary of only fifty words, he or she may be
able to comprehend communication on a much higher level. The child maintains a
level of 'mental grammar' that, according to Jackendoff,
may be completely unconscious (Jackendoff 20).
Similarly, deaf people maintain a form of mental grammar that is
incomprehensible to the hearing population. Unfortunately, the inability of the
deaf to verbally articulate their mental processes has led to the habitual
downgrading of their mental capacities by the hearing population: 'If
great flourishes in English are associated with a refined mind, simple, awkward
speech and gesticulation are associated with a simple mind. Because language
and intellect are so linked in our representation of people (we are surprised
to hear a towering intellect expressed--unless by deliberate intent--in a
Southern drawl or in ungrammatical sentences), deafness seems a defect of
intellect' (Lane 8). The psychology of deafness often reinforces this
misconception. Lane cites a 1985 psychiatric journal which printed the
following fallacy: 'Profound deafness that occurs prior to the acquisition
of verbal language is socially and psychiatrically
devastating' (Lane 35). Such statements are evidence of a refusal to
validate the uniqueness of the deaf community, its language, and its culture.
The traditional attitude of most social scientists toward the deaf community
has been one of paternalism. According to Lane, hearing paternalism
'begins with defective perception, because it superimposes its image of
the familiar world of hearing people on the unfamiliar world of deaf people'
(Lane 37). Quite naturally, with this type of thinking, stereotypes abound.
The language deficiencies of the mentally handicapped likewise prompt
stereotypes and misconceptions about their cognitive abilities. Savage-Rumbaugh and Lewin cite
statistics on the 1.25 million children in the United States who suffer severe
speech impairments due to brain deficiencies (Savage-Rumbaugh
183). These children were traditionally given speech therapy, and the failure
of many to respond to such therapy was felt to be a result of their diminished
mental capacity. Recently, however, such children are being treated using
visual-graphic systems capable of teaching symbolic communication. One such
study of cerebral palsy patients indicated a remarkable improvement in their
social demeanor, work and sentence skills, and ability to take initiative.
Another study of symbolic communication therapy in severely mentally retarded
children reaped remarkable results: 'Individuals for whom all traditional
methods of speech and other language training had failed, had learned to
communicate for the first time in their lives, using (a) computer-based
keyboard lexigram system' (Savage-Rumbaugh and Lewin 193).
The use of a computer-based keyboard lexigram system
was used by Savage-Rumbaugh in her studies of
symbolic communication in apes. The symbols, or lexigrams,
on the keyboard stood for one word. The lexigrams
were built from simple geometric forms and subclassified
according to three different colors (Savage-Rumbaugh
and Lewin 182). The system was called LANA (LANguage Analogue), the same name given to the first chimp
who used it. Lana, the chimp, was given access to the computer on a 24-hour
basis so that she could interact with it even when the researchers were not
present. Her activities on the keyboard were stored in memory. Although Lana
acquired an impressive, working vocabulary, Savage-Rumbaugh
concluded that the chimp's comprehension skills were not highly developed. In
contrast, in later work with Kanzi, Savage-Rumbaugh concluded that he indeed possessed certain
elements of language, although not a true grammar: 'We demonstrate that an
ape, in a communicative environment with humans, develops a productive grammar
uncontaminated by imitation, and most interestingly, invents primitive symbol-ordering
rules that he has not been exposed to in his symbolic environment'
(Savage-Rumbaugh 164).
Savage-Rumbaugh argues that animals have minds
because of their self-awareness and their ability to deceive: 'Evidence of
self-awareness and of deception therefore suggests that apes think of
themselves and other as having knowledge states that differ' (Savage-Rumbaugh 276) . The idea that the knowledge state of one
entity differs from another is central to the theory of conscious mental
ability. It implies that animals believe that other animals have minds, else
why would an animal care about its appearance or about being deceptive?
According to Savage-Rumbaugh, 'lies are
notorious in the animal kingdom' (Savage-Rumbaugh
272). Animals routinely 'play dead' or imitate the behavioral
patterns of other animals in order to elude capture. Studies of baboon and
monkeys indicate their readiness to manipulate the action of other members of
their species in order to achieve selfish ends (Savage-Rumbaugh
272). This brings to mind the aforementioned vervet
monkeys. A related form of deception is the games of pretense that animals
play, frequently alone. Savage-Rumbaugh has observed
chimps playing with imaginary toys and fleeing from make-believe monsters
(Savage-Rumbaugh 277).
Jakendoff cites numerous studies that indicate the
ability of apes to use symbols and, although he argues that apes lack a
'mental grammar' on the same level as humans, no convincing research
exits that explains why apes have this capacity to acquire symbolized language
(Jackendoff 139). Savage-Rumbaugh's
observations lead her to believe that 'chimpanzees can acquire language
skills spontaneously, through social exposure to a language-rich environment,
as human children do.' (Savage-Rumgbaugh and Lewin 177). Some critics suggest that the language tasks
given to apes do not require a great deal of intelligence. Others insist that
the apes' ability is the result of stimulus-response activity or conditioning.
(i.e. the Behaviorists and the Cartesians). As we have already discussed in
class, these theories are being hotly debated today, and it appears as though
the majority believe that cognitive thought is possible in species other than
humans.
Strum reports on Washburn whose research indicates
that baboon aggression is linked to the inability of the ape family to develop
language skills (Strum 145). In the early development of humans, man acquired a
complex social life stemming from his grasp of language. This complex social
life 'modified the human body, emotions and brain. In fact, the specific
part of the brain that makes language possible could really be considered the
'social brain' functioning as a mediator of social pressures and helping to
produce appropriate social actions' (Strum 146). This suggests that the
ape family's lack of language skills has stunted the evolution of their
cognitive abilities.
Strum disagrees with critics who attribute deficient mental abilities to
animals, and cites her studies with baboons as evidence: 'All the evidence
pointed to baboons being remarkably clever social sophisticates in all aspects
of their lives' (Strum 140). Strum found that baboon society exhibited a
stable, female hierarchy unique to the animal world. In studying baboons for
the past fifteen years, she has noted 'extraordinary intelligence,
planning and insight in their interaction with each other' (Strum 128).
Their behavior ranged from comical to aggressive.
The work of Jane Goodall in assessing the
intelligence of apes give further credence to the theory of animal mentation. Goodall spent
twenty-nine years studying chimpanzee behavior in Africa. She concludes:
'All those who have worked long and closely with chimpanzees have no
hesitation in asserting that chimpanzees have emotions similar to those which
in ourselves we label pleasure, joy, sorrow, boredom and so on '
(Rollin 271). Goodall approached her work not only as
a scientist, but as a human being who felt a moral responsibility to the
subjects under study.
Rollin believes that the moral aspect in scientific research involving animals
is lacking because scientists are unwilling to admit the existence of animal mentation. They fear being accused of anthropomorphism! I
believe that they not only fear anthropomorphism, but they are genuinely afraid
of dissipating the thin line that distinguishes the animals from the humans.
This concept of fear is further addressed by Dr. Matt Cartmill
when he reflects that 'Whether we fear or welcome the dissolution of [the
animal human ] boundary (as) the real issue behind much of the recent debate
over primate communication, sociobiology, and human evolution.' (excerpt
from Human Uniqueness in Paleoanthropology). Although
many scientists believe in animal consciousness, they are unwilling to admit it
publicly. As one colleague confided to Rollin, 'I believe it at home, but
I leave it behind when I go to the lab' (Rollin 268). Belief in animal mentation requires value judgments, something which modern
science abhors. For this reason, many in the field are reluctant even to
propose study of the concept. Belief in the cognitive abilities of animals is
crucial to the issue of animal rights and welfare. Currently, traditional
science adopts the viewpoint that animals are incapable of emotions related tot
he satisfaction or non-satisfaction of their needs. Therefore, the humane
treatment of lab animals is not an issue (ala Descartes) According to Rollin,
the only was to convince the skeptics and remedy this mindset is for the study
of animal consciousness to become a moral science: Methodologies must be
devised which maximize the respect for individual animals acknowledging that
without research into animal awareness, moral concern for animals in society
must be limited in both scope and detail, and resulting social policy must
inevitably be ill-founded' (Rollin 270).
To convince the skeptics in the scientific community, research into animal
consciousness must go beyond demonstration of the ability of animals to exhibit
language. As Savage-Rumbaugh states, ' As long
as behavioral scientist follow in the footsteps of Descartes, assuming that nonhuman animals are merely robots made of meat and bone,
they will refuse to give up their paradigms built upon the methods of physics
and chemistry.' (Savage-Rumbaugh & Lewin 255). Language is based on comprehensive.
Comprehensive is exhibited by a wide range of language-related skills. These
include the ability to draw inferences, weighing relevancy's, participation in
social practices, providing justifications, and using language to guide and
plan activities (Atherton and Schwartz 14). Most ape
language studies indicate that animals possess the cognitive aptitude to
perform all these activities, although not at a level of sophistication that
matches human beings. Maybe another way to tackle the question of animal
consciousness would be to try to think in terms of the animal mind instead of
in terms of the human mind. Either way one looks at this issue, after
considering the facts presented in 'Kanzi',
there can be no question as to the validity for the argument that many animals
possess a level of consciousness and understanding.
Politica de confidentialitate | Termeni si conditii de utilizare |
Vizualizari: 2336
Importanta:
Termeni si conditii de utilizare | Contact
© SCRIGROUP 2024 . All rights reserved